MARKS,
ENGELS I LENJIN O
OKOLIŠU I RAZVOJU (1/2) |
|
| Aleksandar Knežević |
Ne laskajmo sebi
suviše zbog naših ljudskih pobjeda nad prirodom Ali ne
laskajmo sebi suviše zbog naših ljudskih pobeda nad prirodom. Za svaku takvu
pobedu ona nam se sveti. Istina, svaka od njih ima u prvom redu one
posljedice na koje smo mi računali, ali u drugom i trećem redu ona ima sasvim
druge, nepredviđene posledice, koje veoma često poništavaju one prve. Ljudi
koji su u Mesopotamiji, Grčkoj, Maloj Aziji i drugde iskrčili šume da bi
dobili ziratnu zemlju nisu ni sanjali da su time položili temelje sadašnjoj
pustoši tih zemalja, lišivši ih zajedno sa šumama i centara za skupljanje i
zadržavanje vlage. Kad su alpski Italijani na južnim padinama planina
iskrčili jelove šume, tako brižljivo čuvane na severnim padinama, nisu ni
slutili da su time posjekli korjen planinskom stočarstvu na svome području;
još manje su slutili da su time svojim planinskim izvorima oduzeli vodu za
najveći deo godine, da bi ti izvori za vrijeme kiša mogli izlivati na ravnicu
još bešnje bujice. Ljudi koji su rasprostranjivali krompir po Evropi nisu
znali da s tim brašnjastim gomoljikama ujedno rasprostranjuju i skrofulozu. I
tako nas činjenice na svakom koraku podsjećaju na to da mi nipošto ne vladamo
prirodom kao što osvajač vlada tuđim narodom, kao neko ko stoji izvan
prirode, nego da svojim mesom, krvlju i mozgom njoj pripadamo i usred nje stojimo,
i da se sva naša vlast nad njom sastoji u tome što nad svim ostalim
stvorovima imamo to preimućstvo da možemo saznavati i pravilno primenjivati
njene zakone. I mi, u
stvari, svakim danom učimo da tačnije razumevamo njene zakone i da saznajemo
bliže i dalje posledice naših zahvata u uobičajeni tok prirode. Osobito
poslije ogromnih uspjeha prirodnih nauka u ovom vijeku, mi smo sve više u
stanju da upoznajemo, a time i
savlađujemo i udaljenije prirodne posledice bar najobičnijih naših operacija
u oblasti proizvodnje. I ukoliko se više to bude dešavalo, utoliko će više
ljudi ne samo opet osećati nego i znati da čine jedinstvo s prirodom. I životinje svojom
djelatnošću mijenjaju prirodu Životinje, kao
što smo već pomenuli, takođe menjaju svojom delatnošću spoljnu prirodu, iako
ne u onolikoj meri kao čovek, i to njihovo menjanje okoline vrši opet, kao
što smo videli, povratan uticaj na svoje uzročnike, izazivajući kod njih promene. Jer se u prirodi ništa ne
zbiva izolovano. Svaka pojava utiče na drugu, i obrnuto i u većini slučajeva
baš zaboravljanje tog svestranog kretanja i uzajamnog delovanja sprečava naše
prirodnjake da jasno vide najjednostavnije stvari. Videli smo kako koze
ometaju ponovno pošumljavanje Grčke; na Svetoj Jeleni uspele su koze i svinje,
koje su onamo dovezli prvi moreplovci, da staru vegetaciju ostrva gotovo
potpuno unište, i tako su pripremile tle za širenje onih biljaka koje su tamo
doneli kasnije pomorci i kolonisti. Ali kad životinje trajno deluju na svoju
okolinu, to se događa nenamerno, i to je, za same te životinje, nešto
slučajno. Ukoliko se ljudi više udaljavaju od životinja, utoliko njihovo
delovanje na prirodu sve više dobija karakter smišljenog, planskog delovanja
prema određenim, unapred poznatim ciljevima. Životinja uništava vegetaciju
jednog predela ne znajući šta radi. Čovek je uništava da bi na oslobođenom
tlu sejao žitarice ili sadio drveće i vinovu lozu, za koje zna da će mu
doneti rod koji nekoliko puta premašuje ono što je posejao ili posadio. On
prenosi korisne biljke i domaće životinje iz jedne zemlje u drugu i tako
menja floru i faunu čitavih delova sveta. Rad je pre svega
proces između čoveka i prirode Rad je pre
svega proces između čoveka i prirode, proces u kome čovek svojom sopstvenom
aktivnošću omogućuje, reguliše i nadzire svoju razmenu materije s prirodom.
Prema prirodnoj materiji on sam istupa kao prirodna sila. On pokreće prirodne
snage svoga tijela, ruke i noge, glavu i šaku da bi prirodnu materiju
prilagodio sebi u obliku upotrebljivom za njegov život. Time što ovim
kretanjem djeluje na prirodu izvan sebe i mijenja je on ujedno mijenja i
svoju sopstvenu prirodu. On razvija snage koje u njoj dremaju, i potčinjava
njihovu igru svojoj vlasti. Ne radi se ovde o prvim životinjskim
instinktivnim oblicima rada. Ono stanje kad se ljudski rad još nije bio
otresao prvog nagonskog oblika daleko je zaostalo u maglama prastarih vremena
za stanjem kad radnik istupa na robnom tržištu kao prodavač sopstvene radne
snage. Mi pretpostavljamo rad u obliku kakav je svojstven samo čoveku. Pauk
vrši operacije slične tkačevim, a gradnjom svojih voštanih komora pčela
postiđuje ponekad ljudskog graditelja. Ali što unapred odvaja i
najgorega graditelja od najbolje pčele jeste da je on svoju komoru izgradio u
glavi pre no što će je izgraditi u vosku. Na završetku procesa rada izlazi
rezultat kakav je na početku procesa već postojao u radnikovoj zamisli, dakle
idealno. Ne postiže on samo promjenu oblika prirodnih stvari; on u njima
ujedno ostvaruje i svoju svrhu koja mu je poznata, koja poput zakona određuje
put i način njegova rađenja, i kojoj mora da potčini svoju volju. A ovo
potčinjavanje nije usamljen čin. Pored naprezanja organa koji rade, traži se
za sve vreme trajanja rada i svrsishodna volja, koja se očituje kao pažnja, i
to tim više što radnika manje bude privlačila sadržina samog rada i način
njegovog izvođenja, dakle što manje on bude uživao u radu kao u igri svojih
sopstvenih telesnih i duhovnih sila. Ukoliko radnik više
osvaja vanjski svijet, utoliko više oduzima sebi životna sredstva Radnik postaje
utoliko siromašniji ukoliko proizvodi više bogatstva, ukoliko njegova
proizvodnja dobiva više na moći i opsegu. Radnik postaje utoliko jeftinija
roba ukoliko stvara više robe. Povećanjem vrijednosti svijeta stvari
raste obezvrjeđivanje čovjekova svijeta u upravnom razmjeru. Rad ne
proizvodi samo robe; on proizvodi sebe sama i radnika kao robu, i to u
razmjeru u kojem uopće proizvodi robe. Ta činjenica izražava samo ovo: da se
predmet proizveden radom, njegov proizvod, suprotstavlja njemu kao tuđe
biće, kao sila nezavisna od proizvođača. Proizvod rada jest rad
koji se fiksirao u jednom predmetu, koji je postao stvar, to je opredmećenje
rada. Ostvarenje [Verwirklichung] rada jest njegovo opredmećenje. Ovo
ostvarenje rada pojavljuje se u nacionalnoekonomskom stanju kao obestvarenje
[Entwirklichung] radnika, opredmećenje kao gubitak i ropstvo predmeta, prisvajanje
kao otuđenje, kao ospoljenje. Ostvarenje
rada toliko se pojavljuje kao obestvarenje, da se radnik obestvaruje do smrti
od gladi. Opredmećenje se toliko pojavljuje kao gubitak predmeta, da je
radnik lišen najnužnijih predmeta, ne samo predmeta za život nego i predmeta
rada. Štoviše, sam rad postaje predmet kojeg se radnik može domoći samo
najvećim naporom i sasvim neredovnim prekidima. Prisvajanje predmeta
pojavljuje se do te mjere kao otuđenje, da ukoliko radnik proizvodi više
predmeta, utoliko može manje posjedovati i utoliko više dospijeva pod vlast
svog proizvoda, kapitala. Sve te
konsekvencije nalaze se u određenju da se radnik prema proizvodu svoga
rada odnosi kao prema tuđem predmetu. Jer prema toj pretpostavci
je jasno: ukoliko se radnik svojim radom više eksteriorizuje, utoliko moćniji
postaje tuđi, predmetni svijet koji on stvara sebi nasuprot, utoliko postaje
siromašniji on sam, njegov unutrašnji svijet, utoliko njemu samome manje
pripada. Razmotrimo sad
pobliže opredmećenje, proizvodnju radnika i u njoj otuđenje,
gubitak predmeta, njegova proizvoda. Radnik ne može
ništa stvarati bez prirode, bez osjetilnog vanjskog svijeta. To
je materijal na kojem se ostvaruje njegov rad, u kojemu je on djelatan, iz
kojega i pomoću kojega on proizvodi. Kao što
priroda, međutim, pruža radu životna sredstva u smislu da rad ne može živjeti
bez predmeta na kojima se vrši, tako ona, s druge strane, pruža i životna
sredstva u užem smislu, naime sredstva za fizičko izdržavanje samog radnika. Dakle, ukoliko
radnik pomoću svoga rada više osvaja vanjski svijet, osjetilnu
prirodu, utoliko više oduzima sebi životna sredstva u dva smisla:
prvo, tako što osjetilni svijet sve više prestaje da bude predmet koji
pripada njegovu radu, životno sredstvo njegova rada; drugo, što
vanjski svijet sve više prestaje da bude životno sredstvo u
neposrednom smislu, sredstvo za fizičko izdržavanje radnika. Nastaviće se
|
|
Let us not flatter ourselves too much for our human
victories over nature But let us not flatter
ourselves too much for our human victories over nature. For every such
victory, nature takes revenge on us. True, each of them has in the first
place the consequences on which we counted, but in the second and third place
it has quite different, unforeseen consequences, which very often cancel out
the first ones. The people who in Mesopotamia, Greece, Asia Minor and
elsewhere cleared the forests to obtain arable land did not even dream that
they were thereby laying the foundations of the present desolation of those
lands, depriving them, together with the forests, of the centers for the
collection and retention of moisture. When the Alpine Italians cleared the
fir forests on the southern slopes of the mountains, so carefully guarded on
the northern slopes, they did not even suspect that they were thereby cutting
off the roots of mountain cattle breeding in their area; still less did they
suspect that they had thereby deprived their mountain springs of water for
the greater part of the year, so that during the rains these springs might
pour down even more furious torrents upon the plain. The people who spread
potatoes throughout Europe did not know that with these floury tubers they
were also spreading scrofula. And so facts remind us at every step that we do
not rule nature as a conqueror rules a foreign people, as someone standing
outside of nature, but that with our flesh, blood, and brain we belong to it
and stand in its midst, and that all our power over it consists in the fact
that we have the advantage over all other creatures of being able to know and
correctly apply its laws. And we are, in fact,
learning every day to understand its laws more accurately and to learn the
closer and more distant consequences of our interventions in the ordinary
course of nature. Especially after the enormous successes of natural science
in this century, we are increasingly able to recognize and thus overcome the
more distant natural consequences of even our most ordinary operations in the
field of production. And the more this happens, the more people will not only
feel again but also know that they are one with nature. Animals also change nature by their activity Animals, as we have
already mentioned, also change external nature by their activity, although
not to the same extent as man, and this change of their environment again, as
we have seen, has a reciprocal effect on its causes, causing changes in them.
For nothing happens in nature in isolation. Each phenomenon affects another,
and vice versa, and in most cases it is precisely the forgetting of this
versatile movement and mutual action that prevents our naturalists from
seeing the simplest things clearly. We have seen how goats hinder the
reforestation of Greece; on St. Helena the goats and pigs, which were brought
there by the first sailors, succeeded in almost completely destroying the old
vegetation of the island, and thus prepared the ground for the spread of
those plants that were brought there later by sailors and colonists. But when
animals permanently affect their environment, this happens unintentionally,
and it is, for the animals themselves, something accidental. The more people
move away from animals, the more their action on nature takes on the
character of deliberate, planned action towards certain, known goals. An
animal destroys the vegetation of a region without knowing what it is doing.
Man destroys it in order to sow grain on the liberated soil or plant trees
and vines, which he knows will bring him a harvest that several times exceeds
what he sowed or planted. He transfers useful plants and domestic animals
from one country to another and thus changes the flora and fauna of entire
parts of the world. Work is above all a process between man and nature Work is above all a
process between man and nature, a process in which man, by his own activity,
enables, regulates, and controls his exchange of matter with nature. He
himself appears as a natural force towards natural matter. He sets in motion
the natural forces of his body, arms and legs, head and hand, in order to
adapt natural matter to himself in a form usable for his life. By acting on
nature outside himself and changing it through this movement, he also changes
his own nature. He develops the forces that lie dormant in it and
subordinates their play to his own power. We are not talking here about the
first instinctive forms of animal labor. The state when human labor had not
yet shaken off the first instinctive form is far behind in the mists of ancient
times the state when the worker appears on the commodity market as a seller
of his own labor power. We assume labor in a form that is peculiar only to
man. The spider performs operations similar to those of a weaver, and by
building its wax chambers, the bee sometimes puts the human builder to shame.
But what distinguishes even the worst builder from the best bee in advance is
that he has built his chamber in his head before he builds it in wax. At the
end of the work process, the result emerges which already existed in the
worker's imagination at the beginning of the process, that is, ideally. He
does not merely achieve a change in the form of natural things; he also
realizes in them his purpose which is known to him, which, like a law,
determines the path and manner of his work, and to which he must subordinate
his will. And this subordination is not an isolated act. In addition to the
exertion of the working organs, a purposeful will is also required throughout
the duration of the work, which manifests itself as attention, and this is
all the more so the less the worker is attracted by the content of the work
itself and the manner of its execution, that is, the less he enjoys work as a
play of his own physical and mental powers. The more the worker conquers the external world, the
more he deprives himself of the means of life The worker becomes the
poorer the more wealth he produces, the more his production gains in power
and scope. The worker becomes the cheaper commodity the more he creates. With
the increase in the value of the world of things, the devaluation of the
world of man increases in direct proportion. Labor does not only produce
commodities; it produces itself and the worker as a commodity, and this in
proportion to the extent to which it produces commodities at all. This fact
expresses only this: that the object produced by labor, its product,
confronts it as an alien being, as a force independent of the producer. The
product of labor is labor that has become fixed in an object, that has become
a thing, that is, the objectification of labor. The realization
[Verwirklichung] of labor is its objectification. This realization of labor
appears in the national economic situation as the derealization
[Entwirklichung] of the worker, objectification as the loss and slavery of
the object, appropriation as alienation, as alienation. The realization of
labor appears to such an extent as derealization that the worker is
derealized to the point of starvation. Objectification appears to such an
extent as the loss of the object that the worker is deprived of the most
necessary objects, not only objects of life but also objects of labor.
Moreover, work itself becomes an object that the worker can achieve only with
the greatest effort and quite irregular interruptions. Appropriation of
objects appears to such an extent as alienation, that if the worker produces
more objects, the less he can own and the more he comes under the control of
his product, capital. All these consequences
are found in the determination that the worker treats the product of his work
as someone else's object. Because according to that assumption it is clear:
if the worker exteriorizes himself more with his work, the more powerful he
becomes, the object world he creates in opposition to himself, the poorer he
himself becomes, his inner world, the less he belongs to himself. Let's now take a
closer look at reification, the production of the worker and in it the
alienation, the loss of the object, its product. The worker cannot
create anything without nature, without the sensory external world. It is the
material on which his work is realized, in which he is active, from which and
with which he produces. Just as nature,
however, provides labor with means of life in the sense that work cannot live
without the objects on which it is performed, so it, on the other hand, also
provides means of life in a narrower sense, namely the means for the physical
support of the worker himself. Therefore, if the
worker through his work conquers the external world, the sensory nature, the
more he takes away his means of life in two senses: first, by the fact that
the sensible world ceases more and more to be an object that belongs to his
work, the means of life of his work; secondly, as the outside world increasingly
ceases to be a means of life in the immediate sense, a means for the physical
support of workers. To be continued .
|